You are not logged in.
#1. Did you know?
The Rutherford Appleton Laboratory is in Oxfordshire, England.
If youre finding area by integrating between 0 and a general x > 0, you must take the modulus of the integrand.
Wow! I thought of Steve Davis and it correctly guessed my character. Id say that was just a fluke.
For a sine wave, the -cosine result doesn't
come up
Whats the problem?
Some friends of mine have come up with some of their own haiku here: clickety click.
Hence
2=2, 2²=4, 2³=8, 2^4=5, 2^5=10, 2^6=9, 2^7=7, 2^8=1
So should 8 be the order of 2? The answer in the book says that it is 10?
Are you familiar with Lagranges theorem? One consequence of Lagrange is that the order of an element of a finite group must divide the order of group. The group youre dealing with is of order 10; hence the possible orders for 2 are 1, 2, 5 and 10. You therefore only need to check 2[sup]1[/sup], 2[sup]2[/sup], 2[sup]5[/sup] and 2[sup]10[/sup].
NB: If youre not familiar with Yorkshire dialect, this joke may not be funny, but well see.
There was this Yorkshire elderly couple, see, and the woman had got cancer and one day she died. There was a funeral for her, she was buried, and then the widowed husband noticed something wrong. The first line of the epitaph on her tombstone was supposed to read SHE WERE THINE but the stonemason had made a mistake and left out the final E so the line read SHE WERE THIN instead. Furious at the masons shoddy work, the widower went to the mason and demanded that the missing E be restored immediately. So the mason went back to his work, and the next day, the man went back to have a look. To his horror, the first line of the epitaph now read: E SHE WERE THIN.
Okay, more ideas. Let
(1) If D varies and the other coefficients are fixed, then [1] is obviously the general solution to the differential equation
(2) If C varies and the other coefficients are fixed, then
and so [1] is the general solution to the differential equation
(3) If B varies and the other coefficients are fixed, then using the same trick in (2) shows that [1] is the general solution to the differential equation
(3) And if A varies and the other coefficients are fixed, then [1] is the general solution to the differential equation
And, for more fun, you can try varying some of the coefficients and keeping the others fixed. For instance, varying two of the coefficients and keeping the other two fixed will result in a second-order differential equation.
For C, I think you can try this: Given
then
Thus
(1) If A > 0, increasing C will make the curve more and more strictly increasing, i.e. make it look more and more like a positively sloped straight line. The curve will have local maximum and minimum points if
and decreasing C further will widen the horizontal distance between the local max and min points.(2) If A < 0, decreasing C will make the curve more and more strictly decreasing, i.e. make it look more and more like a negative sloped straight line. The curve will have local maximum and minimum points if
and increasing C further will widen the horizontal distance between the local max and min points.Obviously varying D just shifts the curve up and down, but varying A can also be fairly easily visualized. If A is positive and you make it more positive, or if its negative and you make it more negative, you squash the curve sideways, making it narrower. This would be because the curve tends to ±∞ more and more quickly as you increase the absolute value of the leading coefficient.
For B and C, things may be more complicated. I experimented with some cubic curves but my results are not very conclusive what actually happens may very well depend on the sign of A. For B this could be what might happen:
Increasing the absolute value of B appears to increase the vertical distance between the local maximum and minimum points. In addition: (a) If A > 0 then (i) if B > 0 and you make it more positive, the curve tends to be shifted in a NW direction, and (ii) if B < 0 and you make it more, the curve tends to be shifted in a SE direction; (b) If A < 0 then (i) if B > 0 and you make it more positive, the curve tends to be shifted in a NE direction, and (ii) if B < 0 and you make it more, the curve tends to be shifted in a SW direction.
is a bijection.
It contains the subset ℝ which is well known to be uncountable. Is that proof enough?
Hi;
Can you prove this using only algebra?
(1) Use induction.
(2) Hint:
I remember people posting messages like "I have been a regular here for a while, and this is my first post ..."
What if we just deleted people like that?
Then they can just re-register, cant they?
Given
, let .Then
and and so .So yes,
.Im sure the other five relations all work out the same way.
If they visit but do not post, they dont need to register as a member and so their username can be deleted anyway. Use common sense.
Oops. I was thinking only of countably infinite there. Why I was doing that I have no idea.
But yes, cxc001s problem clearly takes the term countable to mean finite or countably infinite.
As such, not all countable sets are of the same cardinality of the integers.
So how do I construct the bijective function f:N->S correctly then?
It depends on which how you define finite set. The two most commonly used definitions are:
(1) A set is said to be infinite iff there is a bijection from itself to a proper subset of itself. It is said to be finite iff it is not infinite (i.e. there is no bijection from itself to a proper subset of itself).
From the first definition, we see that ℕ is infinite (e.g. there is a bijection from itself to the set of all even natural numbers). From the second definition, the fact that ℕ is not finite can be proved by induction on n.
Lets do the proof of the problem using both definitions.
(1) Using this definition, it is more straightforward to prove the contrapositive statement: If |ℕ| ≤ |A| then A is infinite. |ℕ| ≤ |A| means there is an injective function f from ℕ into A. Since ℕ is infinite, so is f(ℕ). And since A has an infinite subset, it must itself be infinite.
(2) For this, we use contradiction and the axiom of choice. It may be that you can do it without the axiom of choice (ask Ricky ) but since the axiom of choice simplifies life a great deal, I dont see why I shouldnt be justified in using it.
The fact that there is an injective function from A into ℕ is a simple consequence of the definition of finiteness. Suppose there is a surjective function f from A onto ℕ. By the axiom of choice, there is a bijection f* from a subset A* of A to ℕ (i.e. define the equivalence relation ~ on A by x ~ y iff f(x) = f(y), then select a unique element from each equivalence class to form A* and take f* to be the restriction of f to A*). As A is finite, so is A*. Let g be a bijection from A* to {1,2, ,n} for some natural number n. Then g∘f*[sup]−1[/sup] is a bijection from ℕ to {1,2, ,n}, implying that ℕ is finite a contradiction.
(b) If you complete the square
you can clearly see that
for all real numbers
. You can thus take and ; eliminating giveswhich is the relation all
and must satisfy in order that .(c) Thats correct.
(d) Please define well-known and related to.
Height of the 5th point from the Base =1.5r
No, no, it is (√2)r.