You are not logged in.
Hey guys, i need a HUGE favor, i need the resolution for this 5 questions, its a question of end this year my degree or stay one year just with a subject. Please I am begging, who knows the resolution please say me something.
Part 1: Mathematical Logic
2- Convert the formula into the prenex form: (square root of)x p(x,g) -> ( inverted E )y (square root of) z q (x,y)
I am not the world's expert on logic, but I am sometimes good at these sort of questions.
I apologise if I have got completely the wrong end of the stick with this, but I think you mean:
Not sure what exactly is required by "convert the formula into prenex form". (Is this "prenex normal form" ?)
If it is prenex normal form it may be a good idea to look at the Wikipedia info:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Prenex_normal_form
To me "prenex form" means 'there exists' (inverted E ?), 'for all' (looks like an A written vertically inverted) etc.
also includes NOT, AND, OR, IMPLIES etc. in symbolic form.
I included the "such that" bits to help me understand it, you have not included any because it
is conventional to leave them out in prenex form I suppose. Or have I completely got the wrong
understanding of the meaning of that question?
What else is there to be done ?
I am obviously missing something here.
I think it is a bit mean asking students to convert something like that and memorise all
the rules contained in that link for an exam. Are you revising for an exam ?
How can something depend on the square root of z if z is not included in the predicate ?
Clarification in LaTex:
Is p(x,g) a predicate that does a test upon the variables x and g and gives a "true" or "false" ?
Is q(x,y) similarly defined for x and y giving a "true" or "false" ?
Another question: Do you know about how to convert an implication into a logical statement about
So if A implies B then we mean that if A is true then B must be true.
If A is false then nothing is being stated about B. So B is either true or false for the implication
to still be acceptable.
(A implies B) is considered true if and only if ((A and B are true) OR (A is false))
If A is true and B is false then (A implies B) is considered false.
So I think it results in: (B) OR (NOT A) as the output of the predicate P(A implies B)
(If you are revising for an exam then for goodness sake do some practice questions on this
and whatever else you are supposed to learn.)
(I only know a bit of degree style logic so please double check me on the things in this post
I have already corrected about 10 errors that I have made.)
It appears that you have done the bit to get f(0)=0 which is good, but the second bit where
you need to do a substitution like y = -x you appear not to have done correctly.
I will give you a few more lines of it to give you the idea of what I meant:
Let us assume that the result f(0)=0 is proven.
Now let y = -x
Using the original equation f(x+y) = f(x) + f(y) + 2xy
We get: f(x-x) = f(x) + f(-x) + 2(x)(-x)
Since x-x = 0 the bit in the left hand side can be simplified to f(0)
The bit where we have 2(x)(-x) can be written as -2x^2
So f(0) = f(x) + f(-x) - 2x^2
Using the result from earlier that f(0) = 0 we get:
0 = f(x) + f(-x) - 2x^2
This can be rearranged to give us:
f(x) = 2x^2 - f(-x)
[This was an interesting result, but we cannot eliminate f(-x).]
I am not sure at this point whether it is good style to change the letter that
is used like u = -x (as a substitution) or -u = x
[I now realise that this does not work. Sorry about that bit.]
Sorry about this. I have spotted a flaw in the final part of my proof.
This substitution does not appear to work, although it is confusing and
it is easy to accidentally flip the sign when writing it and think that it
proves that f(x) = f(-x) which would solve the problem.
Edit: Thanks Avon, also thanks to {7/3} for an interesting problem.
I have now read Avon's post, checked it to see that I agree, and yes it does work.
My result f(x) = 2x^2 - f(-x) is not needed so that was a blind alley.
However it is needed to do my y=-x substitution with the function g(x + y) to make the method that follows work.
A few hints that I gave were:
Let y = 0, substitute this into your equation.
Use the fact that (x+0) = x
Simplify where possible. (You can fill in the intermediate steps.)
(.......)
Deduce that f(0) = 0
Start back with the original equation.
Let y = -x
Use the fact that (x-x) = 0
Then substitute the fact that f(0) = 0
Simplify where possible.
[As I have now discovered having checked my work and read Avon's post this does not lead to a solution.]
Try to get a formula for f(x) in terms of x and f(-x)
Then use this result to find what f(-x) in terms of x and f(x).
Make use of things like the fact that (-x)(-x) = x^2
Simplify your answer. Rearrange the equation. Try to make f(x) the subject.
[Actually we cannot get f(x) in terms of x this way. The result is true, but does not solve the problem.
The term of f(-x) cannot be eliminated because it does not always equal f(x).
However if we were allowed to assume that f(x) = f(-x) we could use this result to solve the problem.]
[I discovered later that my proof had a flaw caused by an accidental sign change in my notes.]
I agree with bobbym's answer exactly.
I have decided to hide my comment about a possible method below.
It would be interesting to know how Agnishom got an answer that is very nearly
correct but slightly out. (Assuming of course that bobbym's was right - I think it is.)
It is possible to transform the original wikipedia equation to the equation
Wikipedia stated that:
Now let a=b=c=1
We need a transformation such that:
It can be shown that the following substitution can be used to achieve this:
Using this transformation:
Okay. I will think up some ideas and send you an email.
Okay I can do that. Before I do. There were a few percentage questions in the original 10.
Do you want some extra ones to those? Were the ones I gave you too difficult ?
I have looked at the Wikipedia definition of a "hyperbolic paraboloid" and it gives an equation of:
My immediate intuitive thought is that the expression you gave cannot be rearranged into this.
However what about a rotated version of this ?
The equation that Wikipedia gives for this is:
If a = b then it is not exactly the same as your expression, but bares some resemblance with an extra x^2 term.
If a is not equal to b in magnitude then a y^2 term seems to be needed to make it a proper fit to the equation.
At the time of writing I am not sure whether the expression you gave is another rotation or not possible with any rotation.
My guess at the moment is that it is not possible with any rotation. I do not know how to rotate the equation by an angle
in the +z direction in general, but I would have thought the y^2 term would be non zero.
This is just a guess though so I wonder what other members think about this.
To Mandy: Hi SteveB here.
Send email or post reply please ?
It would be a good idea for you to give me an indication of what you think you would like to do next.
Some good ideas might be:
(1) Continue with those 10 questions from the point that you have got to.
(2) Do more on fraction addition.
(3) Ratio
(4) Percentages
(5) Time. Be more specific because a huge number of maths questions use time in different ways and levels of difficulty.
Yes that was the one I was talking about. Is it better to post to that one or continue the discussion here?
Also is anyone curious like me about the answer to that one?
There is a mathematical topic called "Linear Statistical Modelling" where I have an old text book from about 1999 approx.
I did do some studies to do with this some time ago, however my knowledge is a bit rusty and the software that goes with
the course I can no longer use because it was for my old computer and I only had one years use of the software allowed by
the license agreement anyway. There is a way that an approximate model is used in the textbook, but as I say it was a long
time ago that I studied this. Also if it were an academic question they would give out some test data with questions to guide
the student through it. (Obviously it would not be like that in real life.)
EDIT/FOOTNOTE:
I have looked at the book ("Statistical Modelling Using Genstat") and there is a piece on converting the multinomial
distribution into a Poisson generalized linear model. It is in chapter 12 called "Loglinear models for contingency tables".
A theorem is used where it is basically trying to say that Poisson models for categorical data behave like multinomial
models. At the time of writing I do not fully understand the proof of the theorem so I am not going to paraphrase the proof.
The hypothesis test would use this model with something like what the software calls:
"Stats|Regression Analysis|Generalized Linear| Log-linear" (using the menu system of Genstat)
Of course the software may have changed by now and other software may now be considered better now for some reason.
The software may have been chosen for educational reasons. However it is advisable to use software for this because otherwise
the calculations by hand would be too complicated. It strikes me that a control group that just has the before and after test
but with no induced (bad) taste stage would be needed to avoid confounding the experiment with the effect of the before
part of the test. However the hypothesis test I think would be the above test.
Thankyou anonimnystefy, I have worked it out myself by plugging in the values (57,43,100 etc.) and using an online
integral calculator (because frankly to integrate that one as a pen and paper exercise would be complicated because
apart from having a huge number of terms and a large scope for silly mistakes, it would probably take ages)
reassuringly enough I agree with your answer exactly.
So according to this model the player that lost the contest of 100 games has a 8.16 % (approx.) chance of being the
better of the two players, from a theoretical point of view.
By the way on an entirely different topic (but related to statistics) I remember a post from someone who was doing
some research, and the person wanted help with a hypothesis test for a situation along the following lines:
(I may have changed the problem a little)
You have 100 fish (or n fish perhaps?) in an experiment to do with taste aversion. A before and after trial is performed on each fish.
Before and after the fish is classified according to four categories:
(1) Avoidance of Bait
(2) Approach Bait but does not eat
(3) Small bite/taste of the Bait
(4) Rapid change in swimming speed/motion
These categories give some idea of how each fish responds to some food, and give some idea of the fish in terms
of its reaction to some food, and possibly taste aversion. Whether they are ordinal I am not exactly sure, I think that
ideally they are ordinal, but they could be 4 categories that cannot be put into a precise order. (I need to think about that point.)
Of course at random, there are going to be average proportions for these categories which could be anything between 0 and 1,
and whatever the averages at random there will be a certain degree of variation. We need a hypothesis test ideally that models
the random variation according to a null hypothesis, that gives us some way of deciding whether a statistically significant result
has been obtained at a certain level (eg. p = 0.01 etc. or 99% significance ... ).
I did think that an extension of the binomial distribution might work, except with 4 categories instead of two.
Is this refered to as a multinomial distribution ?
I realise that the post from which I got this happened some time ago (two months approx.) and the person who posted
the problem probably has found out the answer by some method.
Purely out of curiosity, it might be interesting to try to answer this one, however it is a difficult one, and I suspect it probably
requires some proper statistical software to answer this anyway.
Hi;
It is not necessarily true that the victorious player is superior. In the most simplistic sense if we flip a coin 5 times, heads or tails will be victorious with 3 or more wins out of 5. Two players evenly matched ( fair coin ) can produce extremely long runs of such dominance just by luck. Take a random walk for example. The player in the lead will have that lead for more than 90% of the time, even though they are perfectly even. It would be very easy for that player to assume he was much better than the other!
I realise (and did realise) that the victorious player is not necessarily superior.
In fact in my question what I meant was what is the probablility that this "common sense view" is wrong ?
The form of my question was confusing because I used the term "common sense superior" to mean "victorious".
In the long term the more games are played (assuming that the probability of each winning is constant) the better estimate
we get of one player being better than the other modelled by a probability P of one being victorious in a single game.
There may be some use in temporarily assigning the value P = 0.5 for some reason, but the Wikipedia entry I found confusing,
but it does sound quite sophisticated, and it is very unlikely that P is exactly 0.5, I agree with anonimnystefy that if we take
this literally then as the degree of accuracy increases the probability of this converges to zero as the number of decimal places
of the accuracy tends to infinity. In practice we could never have such perfect accuracy, but in that case an interval ought to be
given like: 0.45 to 0.55 or 0.495 to 0.505
However no such range was given. Do we really mean this ? [The range chosen would be an arbitary choice]
In other words would we be likely to want to ask the question in this way ?
Or is it better to ask the question: What is the probability that the non victorious player is better in terms of underlying ability ?
According to the method in the Wikipedia link by anonimnystefy what would the answer be ?
To be quite frank I did not follow the method given by the Wikipedia entry. I could plug in some values and see if I can get
an answer. This did refer to testing a coin for bias, but it might well be applicable to this exercise/puzzle.
Even a perfectly "fair" coin has some degree of bias. I think I remember reading once about an experiment that was done
which established that there was a small bias in a regular coin, however I cannot remember the details and frankly it can
only have been slightly weighted one way or the other.
What is the probability that the apparently inferior player (according to common sense interpretation that the player that won
57 games out of 100 is "superior" and the player that won only 43 is "inferior") is in fact a player whose underlying ability
is greater than the common sense "superior" player with the assumption that a player has greater underlying ability if and
only if the theoretical probability of him/her winning in the long term P is greater than or equal to 0.5 ?
That is the probability of ( P >= 0.5 ) ?
I like SteveB's disproof in #5. Thanks to Nehushtan
Bob Bundy, I am not getting your point. My induction step shows that adding 1 preserves the property.
Thanks Nehushtan, that was a much clearer explanation than mine. Basically it amounted to the same thing that the
case where k=1 does not allow the inductive step to work, because an intermediate horse is needed otherwise we
end up with two equations without a horse color on the other side of the equation, because if the set only has two
horses in it then removing one leaves just one, and of course the equation needs something on both sides, and
the horses from 2 to k are non-existent.
About the Bob Bundy point: anonimnystefy has answered this already, in that Bob has (perhaps like me in my first
post) not read the theorem very well and has interpreted it in a way where the set under consideration is just a
particular set (which could be thought of as being added to by one element each time one is added to n) rather than
ANY set of that size picked from the set of all horses. I realised after studying the question more closely and thinking
about it for longer, that it could not possibly be this problem that was being intended by the author of the book.
If it were that problem then it would be the inductive step that fails and in every case it would fail because if we are
adding a new horse from an outside source from which the theorem is not anything to do with. However this is as
I mentioned earlier not a correct interpretation of the problem, and as far as I know, does not lead to anything particularly
remarkable. It does however show that human error can occur both in producing a new mathematical idea, as well
as spotting the correct flaw (as I managed to get wrong in my post #2 when I jumped to the wrong conclusion regarding
the flaw). Also communicating the idea well can cause problems as I managed to show in my next post on when I had
realised what the flaw was in my head, but did not explain it very well.
To go back to the original problem though: The inductive step does work for k = 2 and all k > 2 as well.
However if we cannot get from case n=1 to case n=2 using the inductive step (which we can't) then this does not make any
difference because the case where n=3 can only be proven by induction if the n=2 case is proven.
The case n=2 really should be proven as a separate case (another basis case), but common sense tells us
that we cannot literally go through an infinite number of horses to show this for every horse set of size 2.
In mathematics a property of the mathematics might give us some way of proving something for an infinite set,
but obviously equal horse color is not likely to have such a property. If it were a real maths problem that we were trying
to solve and the inductive step was not valid for k=1 (but was for k>1) then we would try to solve this case as a special
case unless of course there was some other way round the problem.
Yes I agree with you there. My first post was not really the point where the argument fails.
The problem is not where we take an arbitrary set of size k + 1, but rather the point in my second post.
The inductive step only works if we can argue it on the basis of overlap between smaller subsets.
Take the case where k = 2, since k + 1 is 3 we have {horse1, horse2, horse3} and we could argue that if we have already
proven the case where n = 2 then the two subsets {horse1, horse2} and {horse2, horse3} are the same color because
they are sets of size 2 which contain horses of the same color.
However now let k = 1, since k + 1 is 2 we have {horse1, horse2} the subsets chosen by the inductive step are
{horse1} and {horse2} these do not overlap so we cannot conclude that the horses are the same color. The fact that
the size 1 sets are the same color as themselves is not enough.
So my revised answer is that the inductive step does not work for k = 1 to get us from the case n = 1 to n = 2.
(In other words we cannot jump from saying that every horse is the same color as itself to saying that any pair of
horses are the same color. Obviously if we did find that every pair of horses were the same color, then all of the other
cases would follow. So yes I agree the fact that a set of size k + 1 is taken does not necessarily mean that the inductive
step does not work, and my answer in post #2 was not correct. At the time I had not read the pseudo proof carefully
and perhaps rushed my answer a bit. There are a few minor things about the alleged proof which are not very good style.)
I have thought of another idea for what is wrong:
Are we saying that the hypothesis is true for all sets of horses of that size of of just one particular horse set size?
There is a big difference between "I have one set of one horse which is the same color as itself"
to "All pairwise comparisons of pairs of horses have the same color".
Take the basis case n=1. If we take the first statement to be the interpretation then it is true because we are only comparing
the horse with itself.
However it is nonsense in the second interpretation: If all pairs of sets of horses with n=1 have to be the same color for the basis
case to be true then the basis case is not true.
Are we trying to argue to get from n=1 to n=2 that given that a horse is the same color as itself then if we look at the set
containing both horses take away one horse it is the same as itself therefore n=2 works?
There is an inconsistent phrase in the theorem of "the" set of horses as compared to "a" set of horses. This is a big difference.
Either n=1 just has to represent one isolated set of one horse, or it has to represent every set including every pairwise comparison
between two sets to be valid, otherwise the inductive step will not be valid.
I think that the case for n=1 probably is supposed to be that each horse however chosen is the same color as itself.
However the n=2 case would be that any pair of horses however chosen are the same color.
We obviously cannot get from n=1 to n=2 so there has to be a flaw. If we have two horses {horse1, horse2} then
remove n=1 of them we get {horse1} or {horse2} either way the inductive step from n=1 to n=2 will not be proven.
The fact that the hypothesis holds for the sets individually does not tell us anything about the pairwise comparison between
the two horses. If we number the set from 1 to (2-1) then this is 1 to 1 ie horse1. If we number them from 2 to 2 then this
is horse2. Of course if we could prove the hypothesis for the case n=2 then we would have proven it for all n because if we
can arbitarily choose any pair and show that they have the same color then all horses are the same color.
So yes my revised answer would be that we cannot get from n=1 to n=2. This assumes the interpretation that we are
taking ANY pair of horses for n=2 and not just one isolated set. (If it is an isolated set then all of the n=k to n=k+1
steps are flawed, because we are always taking in a new horse that we don't know anything about.)
The inductive step could be said to work from n=2 to n=3 because each pair is covered by the n=2 case, but if you
go through the inductive step for n=1 to n=2 then of course it is nonsense, because there is no overlap between the
one size smaller subsets of {horse1, horse2}.
(2) If S is true for n = k, then S is true for n = k + 1.
The horses can be numbered from 1 to k + 1.
I think that the flaw in the argument is that you have to start by assuming that it is true for n=k then show that it follows
that it is true for n=k+1.
The statement "The horses can be numbered from 1 to k + 1" means that you are cheating by assuming that the statement is
true for n=k+1 and then "proving" that it is true for n=k+1
The horses can only be numbered from 1 to k. So when you add the k+1st horse it can of course be different.
For the sake of convention, let this be already done.
Removing Horse #1, we are left with k horses.
So here, we are only left with k-1 horses. We now have to add two horses to get to k+1
One of these is the same color, but the other might not be.
(At least that is what I think. I wonder what the more experienced MIF users think of this problem.)
The image to illustrate the above post should be in this post. I have noticed that you cannot type in any Latex in the same
post as an image upload.
Note that the top left and top right illustrations both represent the fractions (1/3) = (2/6) = (6/18)
The middle two represent (5/6) = (15/18)
The lowest two represent the answer to the addition: (21/18) = (7/6) [As a mixed number this is 1 and a sixth see Latex in above post.]
Question to Mandy: Have you understood this illustration ? Do you have any questions about it ?
I have thought of a good illustration for the adding of (1/3) + (5/6) = (2/6) + (5/6) = (7/6)
or alternatively (1/3) + (5/6) = (6/18) + (15/18) = (21/18) = (7/6)
Both are the same calculation, but with different denominators. (6 and 18 respectively)
(a) 11/36
(b) 2/5
I am absolutely sure about the first one, but have a slight nagging doubt about the second.
The thing that occurs to me is Bayes Theorem, and I haven't studied that for a long time.
I therefore decided to think about how many possible combinations added to 8:
6,2
5,3
4,4
3,5
2,6
Then noticed that two of them contained a six. So (2/5)
The thing that made me think of Bayes was that it was "something given something else", but I cannot think how
Bayes could be used in this example. Perhaps it is ((2/36)/(5/36))
Bayes formula would be: P(K|C) = P(KC)/P(C)
So would it be valid to let P(KC) be the chance of getting an 8 which also contains a six ?
With P(C) as the chance of getting a total of 8.
With P(K) as the chance of the role containing a six.
With P(K|C) as the chance of the role containing a six given that the total is 8.
(Someone needs to check all of that because I am not sure of it. Haven't done this for ages.)
Here is an interesting variant of your equation
Suppose iZ=(-4) power 2/3
Using basically the same method with Z = x + yi
I have got these solutions:
(1) x = 0 , y = -2.51984209979
(2) x = 2.18224727194 , y = 1.25992104989
(3) x = -2.18224727194 , y = 1.25992104989
(Interestingly the division by i has had the effect of a multiplication by -i upon the solutions.)
Then squareroot(iZ) = minus cuberoot 16
Can you solve that one?
Fot this I have got:
(1) x = 0 , y = -6.34960420787
(2) x = 5.49891854799 , y = 3.17480210394
(3) x = -5.49891854799 , y = 3.17480210394
(This change has had the effect of a further multiplication by the positive real cube root of 16.)
How many square roots does i have?
I would say 2.
EDIT: I have looked at some Wikipedia entries on this topic and Wikipedia does explain this quite well. It appears, if I am
understanding things correctly, that there is a serious problem that occurs if you have a function like
I did try calculating (-1)^(pi) on my calculator that allows complex numbers. It did give an answer that was a complex
number, but I suspect that what it is doing is rounding pi off to a certain number of decimal places and then working it
out using the rational number definition. If the (+/-) sign (or real/non real status) of these answers depend upon whether the
numerator/denominator are odd/even in their lowest terms then we cannot converge to the correct answer with increasing accuracy.
You cannot really argue for instance that you can converge to a solution by taking increasingly large numbers of terms if when
doing so there are cliff edge gradients with very small changes in R.
When considered in modulus/argument form we can be certain of the modulus of a solution to a negative number raised to an
irrational power, but the argument (angle in a complex number diagram) can be argued to have an infinite number of possible
values with arbitary choice of 2(pi)n [with integer valued n] added to the angle before multiplying by the irrational number.
When we convert the angle back into the correct range there are going to be an endless (countably infinite) series of new solutions
for the angle. So really any angle is as good as any other on the circle that is created. Consistent inverses are probably not going to
trace the answer back to the original negative exponential base. I did originally have the naive idea that you might be able to put the
negative number through a function to a magic complex number and then back again with the same function using the reciprocal of
the power index, but if there are an infinite number of solutions to both functions then to say the result is ambiguous is putting it
rather mildly.
In fact strictly speaking the same logic applies even to a positive number raised to an irrational power, in that it has infinitely
many solutions derived by adding multiples of 2(pi)n and mutiplying by the irrational number then adjusting to the correct angle
range.
However it does of course give a clear unambiguous result provided we simply take the conventional positive real solution, with
of course no sign problem, and all of the required continuous convergence properties.
Looking on the bright side this has given me a quick refresher course in complex numbers, on the less bright side I made quite
a big mistake in suggesting that (-4)^(2/3) had no real solution, when the ordinary mathematical solution does actually work.
Had the problem been (-4)^(3/2) there would have been a necessity then for an imaginary term and so complex numbers would
have been much more relevant (no real solution to the square root of -64 is possible).
You have got a good point there.
It seems that the real solution does work after all.
If you cube the real solution you get 16, then take the negative square root.
One of my graphics calculators does not even accept the input, and the other gives the first of my complex number answers.
Following a recent thread in the "help me" section I became curious about the following alternative interpretation of one of the
questions. The person who started the thread was actually only wanting help with basic integer power functions, but it got
me thinking about what happens in more complicated questions like raising a negative number to a rational power:
[EDIT: My initial thoughts on this were a bit naive. I have tried to tidy up my many mistakes a bit, but there might be a few still.
A better question might have been to ask: It is all very well defining the result, but is it well defined, and are there good
continuous function properties to make raising a negative number to a non-integer power valid? Suppose for example that we
re-write the rational number as (4/6) or (6/9) etc. (as is not allowed conventionally) do we get the number of solutions using
complex numbers that the denominator dictates and is there a logical inconsistency here ?]
[EDIT: Actually the real solution is a valid answer. Complex number solutions do not in fact really resolve the problem that
I had identified. The problem is bound to occur with a negative base raised to a non integer power, given that there is an
alternating sign created by the fact that with an even number of multiplications of a negative number the result is a positive
number, but with an odd number of terms the result is negative. You can in fact get a postive real solution in this case as
Mrwhy has pointed out. The number 3 as the denominator allows 3 solutions with two requiring i terms, and with one real solution.
However you can understand that I was a little uncomfortable that you cannot of course literally split an alternating sign sequence
to include only 2 thirds of a negative term. Also I do still think that, although this is rather unconventional, you could argue that
if you do not specify that the fraction has to be cancelled into a pair of coprime integers then chaos is possible because an infinite
number of solutions is possible for the same fraction because the number of solutions depends upon the denominator.]
In other words: (to the limits of the calculator display)
As a result of the comment below I will also add:
Also I did realise afterwards that the modulus and angle/argument method could be used:
So let us first work out (-4) ^ 2
Well this is 16 because (-4) ^ 2 = (-4) x (-4) = -(-(16)) = 16
Then we get (16 / 3)
So (((-4) ^ 2)/3) = (16/3)
On the other hand: -((4^2)/3) = -(16/3)
Now how about ((-4) ^ 2) / ((-4) ^ 3) = 16/(-64) = 1/(-4) = -(1/4)
If there are an odd number of negative terms in a multiplication then the result is negative.
If there are an even number of negative terms in a multiplication then the result is positive.
A number to the power of 2 means that you find the square of it. (eg. 5 ^ 2 = 25)
Be careful when squaring a negative number because when you multiply a number by itself the signs cancel.
So for example if it were (-5) ^ 2 the (-5) x (-5) would be plus 25. (Obviously yours was (-4) ^ 2 )
I presume you know how to divide by 3 (?)
In general raising a number to the power of something (assuming it is a whole number) means that it is muliplied by itself
that many times. So (-5) ^ 3 = (-5) x (-5) x (-5) [Notice that it is negative because there are 3 negatives here]
You could regard this as (-5) ^ 3 = (1) x (-5) x (-5) x (-5) = -125 [EDIT: Sorry there was a typo there]
and that (-5) ^ 2 = (1) x (-5) x (-5) = 25
If you raise a number to the power of zero then this is always 1.
So in my example of 5 :
5 ^ 0 = 1
I have made up my own example there to make sure I am not giving away the answer.
5 ^ (1/2) = (square root of 5)
5 ^ (1/3) = (cube root of 5)
5 ^ (2/3) = (cube root of 5 squared)
Also note that if the power is negative then:
5 ^ (-1) = (1/5)
5 ^ (-2) = (1/25)
5 ^ (-3) = (1/125)
When you say " (-4) to the power of 2 divided by 3 " do you mean (-4) ^ (2/3) or (((-4)^2) / 3) ? [These are not the same]
(EDIT: The first of these is very difficult and requires complex number theory, but the second is not too difficult.)
(EDIT2: Actually the real solution does work so the cube root of 4 squared is okay.)